Skip to content

Past Workshops and Events

Past Workshops and Events

Ethics and Public Policy Working Group


Workshops:

March 29, 2024, 10am ET (Zoom) Author Meets Critics: Jonathan Wolff (University of Oxford) and Avner De-Shalit (The Hebrew University of Jerusalem), City of Equals, Oxford University Press, 2024.

Access the book for free here!

Critics: Katarina Pitasse Fragoso (Goethe-Universität Frankfurt) and B.R. van Leeuwen (Radboud University)

Abstract: When we think about equality in the city, we are very likely to think first of the wide and growing divide between rich and poor, in material terms. Yet when we think more about a ‘city of equals’ it becomes apparent that how people feel treated by the city and those around them, and whether they can live according to their values, are much more central. Accordingly, based on the authors’ reflections, a multi-disciplinary literature review, and, distinctively, more than 180 interviews in ten cities in six countries, the book offers an account of a city of equals based on the idea that it should give each of its city-zens a secure sense of place or belonging. Four underlying values structure this account. First, access to the goods and services of the city should not be based purely on the market. Second, each city-zen should be able to live a life they find meaningful. Third, there should be diversity and wide social mixing. Fourth, there should be ‘non-deferential inclusion’, that is, each person in the city should be able to get access to what they are entitled to without being treated as less worthy than others. They should be able to enjoy their rights without bowing and scraping, waiting longer than others, or going through special bureaucratic hurdles. In sum, in a city of equals each person is proud of their city and has the (justified) feeling that their city is proud of (people like) them.


February 16, 2024 10:00am ET Annabelle Lever, Professor, Sciences Po, Permanent Researcher, Centre de Recherches Politiques de Sciences Po

Title: “The Right to Stand, The Right to Vote and the Democratic Value of Elections”

Abstract: Democratic elections are meant to express the political authority and agency of ordinary citizens: people who, despite lacking special virtues, knowledge, or resources, are able, and entitled, to govern themselves. If that is what democracy is, on widely shared premises about its nature and importance, there is something puzzling about the way philosophers, social scientists and citizens talk about it, and think about its practice. Given this picture of democracy we might expect them to be as keen to debate the content and justification of the right to stand as candidates for electoral office, and to serve if selected (‘the right to stand’ for short) as to debate their rights to vote.  Yet while the former gets lots of attention, the right to stand is the neglected step-child of democratic theory. This talk (and paper) aim to rectify that neglect, and the difficulties it poses for efforts to distinguish the democratic value of elections, from their value to oligarchic, technocratic and authoritarian regimes.


January 26, 2024 10:00am ET Matthew Adler, Richard A. Horvitz Professor of Law, Professor of Economics, Philosophy and Public Policy, Duke University

Title: “Narrowly Person-Affecting Axiology: Paretian, Equity-Regarding, Desert-Neutral, and Repugnant”

Abstract: The narrow all-things-considered person-affecting principle states: one outcome is not morally better than a second unless better for at least one person. The narrow in-a-respect person-affecting principle states: one outcome is not morally better than a second in any respect unless better for at least one person. 

These principles have been much discussed, often critically.  In the variable-population context, the narrow all-things-considered person-affecting principle has wildly counterintuitive implications—if, as is commonly assumed, the well-being of an existing person cannot be compared with their nonexistence. In the fixed-population context, the narrow in-a-respect person-affecting principle has been decried by Larry Temkin, who argues that it ignores the value of equality. More surprisingly, that principle is rejected even by some prioritarians. 

This paper seeks to bring clarity to the debate about the principles, by studying the underlying axiology that warrants them. A narrow person-affecting axiology (NPA axiology) is such that individuals’ well-being gains and losses are the fundamental pro tanto moral factors determining the moral ranking of outcomes. NPA axiology is precisified via a specific model of how losses and gains determine moral betterness: the claims-across-outcomes model. A claim is a relation between a given individual and a pair of outcomes, with different possible valences: if an individual is better off in outcome than y, they have a claim in favor of over y; if they are equally well off, they have a null claim; if they are incomparably well off, they have an incomparable claim. Non-null claims also have a strength—determined both by the individual’s well-being and, potentially, by non-well-being features of them (desert). 

NPA axiology without well-being comparisons to nonexistence is a nonstarter. Instead, this paper studies NPA axiology on the premise (defended by Gustaf Arrhenius, Nils Holtug, and Wlodek Rabinowicz) that such comparisons are possible. With this premise in hand, and using the claims-across-outcomes model, the paper argues that NPA axiology yields an outcome ranking that: satisfies the Pareto principles; is equity-regarding, in the sense of satisfying the Pigou-Dalton principle; is neutral to desert (it turns out that allowing desert to influence claim strength produces serious difficulties); and leads to the Repugnant Conclusion.


December 1, 2023 10:00am ET Anna Alexandrova, Professor in Philosophy of Science, Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Cambridge

Title: “Value of Measurement and Measurement of Value”

Abstract: Suppose researchers study phenomena whose definition requires a value judgment about what is good, just, or healthy. How should they justify their decision to measure this phenomenon and the specific measures they adopt? No scientific expertise on its own supplies such a justification. A democratic approach would call for involvement of stakeholders with relevant expertise. I report on joint work with Mark Fabian and a UK anti-poverty charity Turn2us to implement inclusive practices for measurement of thriving. However, there are projects where such a participatory approach would not work and we thus need a broader set of principles.


October 6, 2023 10:30am ET Joseph Millum, Senior Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, St. Andrews University

Title: Valuing Interventions That Affect Procreation

Abstract: Within health care systems, limited resources mean that not all interventions can be provided to those who could benefit from them. The decisions about how to allocate limited resources for health care should ideally be made on the basis of evidence and defensible ethical principles. Such decisions require, at a minimum, assessment of the costs and the expected outcomes of alternative health care interventions. For example, many health care systems make some use of cost-effectiveness analysis to compare alternative interventions on the basis of their monetary costs and their effects on health-related quality of life. 

Some medical interventions are not just intended to improve health but also to enable or prevent procreation. The provision of condoms, for example, has multiple desired effects: it allows couples greater control over whether and when they reproduce, condoms protect the user and their sexual partners against sexually transmitted infections, and greater condom use can reduce birth rates. But how should these different effects be evaluated and compared? In this paper, we assess the defensibility of different methods for evaluating the effects of health interventions that affect procreation. We begin with an overview of current practice, which gives an idea of the range of outcomes that evaluative methods take into account and the individuals or entities who are taken to have standing. The overview reveals two principled ways of valuing interventions that affect procreation: the intermediate outcomes approach and the complete accounting approach. Each faces serious challenges. Further, both fail to account for the value of reproductive autonomy—that is, the value to individuals of having the power to choose whether and when to procreate. This problem suggests the possibility of a third approach, which we label the reproductive rights approach. We explain what that approach would entail and note a couple of challenges it would have to overcome. We conclude with some suggestions for choosing an appropriate method.

September 22, 2023 10:30am ET Jessica Flanigan, Associate Professor, Leadership Studies, Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and Law, Richard L. Morrill Chair in Ethics & Democratic Values, University of Richmond

Title: Merely Adequate Motherhood

Abstract: I argue that that children are entitled to be parented by people whose parenting meets a standard of “mere adequacy.” The merely adequate parent is someone who is sufficiently loving and non-abusive, but who may not do the best job at parenting compared to alternative caregivers. Children are not entitled to the best available parent, and parents are not obligated to be the best parents for their children. The first argument for this claim follows from the empirical premise that merely adequate parents are not significantly worse for children than the best available parents would be. Above a standard of adequacy, parenting has limited effects on children’s wellbeing. Nor do differences in parental quality translate to differences in many of the long-term outcomes and opportunities that proponents of high standards parenting purport to care about. The second argument in defense of mere adequacy also appeals to an empirical premise, which is that it is often counterproductive for parents to hold themselves to very high parental standards. Insofar as these empirical claims are controversial, there are moral reasons to adopt a presumption in favor of mere adequacy and against high standards. For one thing, high standards for parenting have negative externalities for women, especially during pregnancy and birth. High standards parenting norms are also harmful to political communities more generally insofar as they discourage people from having children. Finally, high standards parenting prompts people to evaluate parents in comparative terms, whereas a mere adequacy standard focuses conversations about parenting on non-comparative values. Assessments of individual parental quality, which sometimes inform decisions about parental rights, should be made on the basis of non-comparative considerations rather than comparisons to other possible parents. 

April 28, 2023 9:00am-10:30am EDT: Claudio López-Guerra, Associate Professor, Department of Political Science, Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and Law Program, University of Richmond

Title: Public Harm, Fairness, and Political Equality

Abstract: This paper is an (incomplete) draft of a chapter for a book project that defends a novel conception of political equality. The chapter addresses the following question: How should the costs of the unjustifiable risks that policymakers often take be allocated when they ripen into harm? To be more precise, should public officers who take impermissible risks internalize the costs of public harm? If so, how? This chapter provides an account of wrongful political risk-taking and public harm, and on that basis defends the following two claims. (1) Fairness requires that rulers bear the costs of the harm caused by the risks they create by acting in violation of their moral duties. (2) Realizing equal subjection—the novel conception of political equality advanced in the book—is necessary in order to make rulers internalize the costs of public harm. It follows that equal subjection is required by fairness: democratic accountability, the criminal law, and ex post compensation are inadequate.


March 31, 2023, 11:00am-12:30pm EDT: Juan Espíndola, Assistant Professor, Institute for Philosophical Research, National Autonomous University of Mexico 

Title: Transitional Justice, Social Media, and Responsibility: A Conceptual and Normative Framework

Abstract: More and more, Big Tech companies stand accused of enabling human rights violations. The proliferation of toxic speech in their digital platforms has been in the background of recent episodes of mass atrocity, the most salient of which recently transpired in Myanmar, where the military and nationalist groups used Facebook to dehumanize the Rohingya minority and instigate genocidal acts against it. The involvement of Big Tech companies in mass atrocity raises multiple challenges for the aspiration of transitional justice processes to hold wrongdoers accountable. The main challenge is to properly conceptualize Facebook’s responsibility for the circulation of toxic speech. On one view, endorsed by the corporation itself, Facebook can be absolved from any significant share of responsibility for these atrocities because toxic speech is the speech of third parties, hosted but neither created nor endorsed by the company; if anything, Facebook is responsible for failing to anticipate and swiftly remove that speech. This paper will argue that this view is mistaken. Facebook’s business model relies on the manipulation of its users. This fact alone turns the company into a co-creator of toxic speech rather than a mere transmitter of the speech of others. The implication is that Facebook’s responsibility for the dissemination of toxic speech is greater than usually credited, and this matters for how Facebook—and technological corporations like it—enter transitional justice processes.    


January 27, 2023, 9:00am-10:30am EST: Alexandra Oprea, Assistant Professor, Department of Political Science, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill and Daniel J. Stephens, Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Duke Kunshan

Title: “Democratic Risks (or The Risks of Being a Voter)”

Abstract: In this paper, we highlight a frequently ignored aspect of being a democratic citizen with the right to vote, namely that even before exercising one’s right to vote, the franchise brings with it certain risks. These risks come from being targeted by political actors seeking to influence one’s voting behavior. Mobilization strategies that rely on stoking fear, outrage, anger, and partisan animosity, for example, are especially likely to harm the targeted voters. Our paper provides an etiology and taxonomy of the different risks associated with the franchise, clarifying the sources of these risks and the types of harm that different categories of risk might translate into. We then turn to the normative implications of this new understanding of democratic risks for democratic institutions. Our assessment of risks reveals that different electoral systems carry different degrees of risk. Some democratic risks can and should be reduced or mitigated through electoral reforms or other changes in public policy. Moreover, the presence of democratic risks invites us to rethink prevalent conceptions of civic virtue with implications for civic education policy.


November 11, 2022, 9:00am-10:30am EST: Anca Gheaus, Assistant Professor, Department of Political Science, Central European University

Title: “Inheritance in Unjust Circumstances”

Abstract: I assume that we should abolish inheritance in order to fund justice-promoting policies, including an adequate and robust safety net. This paper argues that in unjust societies, especially those that lack such safety nets, parents do no wrong in bequeathing to their children. In unjust societies both procreative duty and parental concern justify bequest as insurance against some forms of misfortune. The justified bequests, while limited both in size and in form, may however be very substantial and therefore impede egalitarian reforms. I conclude that procreative duty and parental love provide (would-be) parents with special – and powerful – reasons to support the introduction of public safety nets.


October 14, 2022, 9:00am-10:30am EDT: Daniel Engster, Professor, Hobby School of Public Affairs, University of Houston

Title: “Responsive Bureaucracy: Toward a Theory of Public Administration for Liberal Democracy”

Abstract: Liberal-democratic theorists have often looked to the hierarchical, compliance model of bureaucratic responsibility to maintain popular control over the state administration and protect the citizenry from bureaucratic domination. Public administration scholars and, more recently, political theorists have criticized this model, however, for misdescribing the role that public administrators actually play in modern liberal-democratic states and have offered other models for subjecting the bureaucracy to popular control, most notably, regime values theory and participatory bureaucracy.

This paper extends the critique of the compliance model and offers a fourth model of the legitimate role of public administration within liberal democracy: responsive bureaucracy. The compliance model is not just descriptively inaccurate, by my account, but inconsistent with core principles of liberal-democratic theory. It represents an authoritarian implant into a governing system that requires public administrators to play a discretionary role in co-producing the laws with legislators. Regime values theory and participatory bureaucracy partially address the problems with the compliance model by making administrative policy implementation more accountable and responsive to the people, but both are insufficient because they leave citizens subject to the implementation of general laws without sufficient control over the process. The particular control that the state now exercises over individuals through the public administration requires new modes of particular citizen control over the public administration to mitigate the threat of domination.

The theory of responsive bureaucracy answers this challenge. Responsive bureaucracy retains elements of the compliance, regime values, and participatory theories of bureaucratic responsibility but highlights the important role street-level bureaucrats can play in giving individuals some say-so over how the laws are applied to them, thus allowing them to avoid domination in their daily encounters with the state and enhancing its normative legitimacy. Responsive bureaucracy represents, I suggest, a theory of public administration most suitable for liberal-democracy.


September 16, 2022, 9:00am-10:30am EDT: Johanna Thoma, Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Logic, and Scientific Method, London School of Economics

Title: “The Democratic Challenge for Policy-Relevant Social Science”

Abstract: Can policy-relevant social science offer action-guidance without violating some basic liberal democratic values? Consider the following claims I take to be relatively uncontroversial and that I will elaborate on in the talk:

  • It is desirable for social science to offer useful action-guidance for public policy.
  • Policy-relevant social scientific indicators are often value-laden, e.g. measures of thick concepts such as poverty, health, economic welfare, happiness, or the cost of living.
  • Reasonable people often disagree about the values captured by such social scientific indicators, both about how to understand them and about their importance.
  • The more aggregate a social scientific indicator is, the more likely such disagreement is, and the more unlikely it is such disagreement can be resolved conclusively in a process of public deliberation.
  • Public decision-making requires aggregation: Public policy typically has a wide variety of impacts affecting various different people and locations at different times. To be able to make an all-things considered choice, aggregate measures of these effects are needed, and the final choice itself must be based on a weighing of all these effects.

Using the example of well-being indicators, I show how these claims together make it challenging to reconcile action-guidance and helping rather than undermining liberal democracy. To achieve action-guidance, many social scientists have argued in favour of “master indicators”, such as the human development index (HDI) or subjective well-being adjusted life years (WELLBYs) as providing a single metric for policy evaluation in terms of wellbeing. By their very nature, such indicators must settle many contentious moral questions about the nature and aggregation of wellbeing. I argue that there is a two-fold threat to liberal democracy (on all prominent conceptions) coming from giving privileged status to such master indicators: Contentious moral questions are settled by social scientists without, or with insufficient democratic input; and insofar as there is a lack of (knowledge of) alternative indicators, those who do not share the value pre-suppositions of the dominant indicator find themselves at an epistemic disadvantage in public deliberation, without reliable knowledge of how different policies fare in relation to their own moral views. Philosophers concerned with the democratic legitimacy of indicators of value-laden concepts, on the other hand, have proposed ways of democratizing measurement, by involving stakeholders in the development of indicators. However, I argue that unless there is a prospect of a broad consensus on the right measurement through public deliberation, we will still end up with indicators that leave parts of the population at an epistemic disadvantage. And there is only prospect for such consensus in the case of more low-level and contextual indicators. These do not lend themselves well to aggregation, and in any case the correct way to aggregate is itself likely to be subject to irresolvable disagreement. This approach thus does not offer useful action-guidance for large scale policy interventions. I end by sketching what I take to be the best way forward, which involves the use of publicly accessible dashboards of multiple indicators and/or tools that allow policy-makers and the public to adjust the weightings of different components of aggregate indicators.


April 29, 2022, 11:00am-12:30pm EST: Matthew Adams, Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Indiana University and Johannes Himmelreich, Assistant Professor, Department of Public Administration and International Affairs, Maxwell School of Citizenship and Public Affairs, Syracuse University

Title: “The Regress Problem for Experiments in Living”

Abstract: An emerging body of literature defends experiments in living as a distinctive and preferable way of doing political philosophy. Proponents are united by a focus on the epistemic role of experiments in living and by the claim that experiments in living not only (a) provide certain sui generisinsights into normative principles that regulate political institutions, but also (b) ground such institutions’ practical authority. In this paper, we present a regress problem: Experiments in living presuppose theories of the same kind that they are meant to be testing.

We identify two kinds of such theoretical presuppositions: (I) conditions of permissible conduct, and (II) conditions of experimental success. Most proponents of experiments in living state the former, few give their account of the latter. Muldoon, for example, states that “collective experiments demand the endorsement of all those involved, or at least all adults involved.”

We argue that all plausible candidate presuppositions are problematic. Against what proponents of experiments in living claim, these presuppositions are not innocuous or “normatively thin”. In this talk we concentrate on permissible conduct for reasons of time. We raise problems for each and argue that the prospects of experiments in living offering a distinctive and preferable way of doing political philosophy are small.


February 18, 2022, 1:00pm-2:30pm EST: Joseph Heath, Professor, Department of Philosophy, Munk School of Global Affairs and Public Policy, University of Toronto

Title: “Anodyne Privatization”

Abstract: Public debate over the privatization of state services often exhibits a Manichean tone, as though the boundary between the public and private sectors was the site of an epochal struggle between good and evil, with the state on one side, representing the forces of justice, and the private sector on the other, representing the greed of capital. Discussion of the issue among political philosophers has been somewhat more nuanced, yet there is still a tendency to treat privatization as a unitary phenomenon, the desirability of which can be determined in the abstract, on the basis of fundamental principles of justice. On top of this, the assumption remains widespread that all those who support the welfare state, along with its central mission of attenuating the injustices generated by the market, should be opposed to privatization in all forms. Thus a great deal of energy has been invested in the task of producing increasingly clever arguments against privatization (with particular emphasis on considerations that rule it out on deontological grounds), without much attention to the administrative difficulties that arose within the public sector that provided the primary motivation for it. My central ambition in this paper will be to explain why someone who is a supporter of the welfare state might also support the privatization of certain state services, in certain cases. A great deal of the philosophical literature has focused on the most problematic privatization initiatives, especially the introduction of private prisons and military contractors. As a counterpoint to this, I would like to describe a set of anodyne privatizations, understood as privatizations that no reasonable person could object to. This provides a useful framework for assessing the acceptability of any particular privatization proposal, because most can be situated between these two extremes. The first step in developing this analysis involves showing that privatization is not a unitary phenomenon. Most importantly, there are different types of privatization, and confusingly, different degrees of privatization. There are also importantly different motives for privatization. Once it is made clear that a half-dozen quite different phenomena are routinely lumped together under the heading of “privatization,” it becomes far less surprising to discover that there are important normative differences between these various initiatives, which might lead a reasonable person to support some, but not others. Thus the normative assessment of privatization must be a great deal more nuanced than it has been, or than the current tenor of the philosophical literature encourages.


January 21, 2022, 11:00am-12:30pm EST: Emily McTernan, Associate Professor, Department of Political Science, University College London

Title: “Freedom of Encounter? Free Association in the Aftermath of Lockdowns”

Abstract: During the covid-19 pandemic, lockdowns have seen park benches taped off, church doors locked, playgrounds padlocked, and cafes and bars closed. In some countries, many ordinary social interactions were banned, such as going on a walk with friends or having family over for lunch. These restrictions made vivid the importance of a relatively philosophically neglected liberty, at least compared to free speech: freedom of association. In this paper, I argue that the experience of lockdowns also suggests to us something about what kinds of association have significance. One of the effects of lockdowns was to radically restrict or eliminate our loose and informal associations, such as those amongst like-minded citizens chatting in a bar; or between acquaintances at work or other loose friendships; or the associations formed between, say, coffee seller and regular customers; or amongst parents chatting while their children play at the playground. This paper examines the importance of such associations – or, perhaps better described, of these encounters with others. I argue that many of the key values that underpin our commitment to freedom of association could also underpin what one might call ‘freedom of encounter’.


November 19, 2021, 9:30am-11:00am EST Andreas T. Schmidt Associate Professor in Political Philosophy, Faculty of Philosophy, University of Groningen

Title: “Do We Have Too Much Choice?”

Abstract: In institutional design, securing freedom of choice for individuals is clearly important. But how much choice should we aim for? Various theorists – including Gerald Dworkin, Joseph Raz, and Barry Schwartz – argue that above some level, choice seems to improve neither wellbeing nor autonomy. Worse still, much psychology research suggests that too much choice even makes us worse off. Such reasons suggest we should adopt the Sufficiency View: increasing choice is only important up to a sufficiency level L, where is not too far from the level enjoyed by well-off citizens in rich liberal countries today. I argue that we should reject the Sufficiency View and accept Liberal Optimism instead: expanding freedom of choice should remain an important priority even far beyond levels enjoyed in rich liberal countries today. I argue that none of the arguments given for the Sufficiency View work. Importantly, neither psychological evidence nor any broader social trends support it. If anything, they support Liberal Optimism instead. I also indicate why further increases are possible and desirable and briefly sketch some implications for debates around immigration, economic growth and markets, and the value of community.

October 15, 2021, 9:30am-11:00am EDT Mollie Gerver, Lecturer (Assistant Professor) in Political Theory, Department of Government, University of Essex

Title: “Asylum Offsetting”

Abstract: States have an obligation to assist refugees, but some states assist refugees via means other than granting them asylum. In other words, they offset their failure to grant refugees asylum by helping refugees in other ways, such as by sending them aid in camps in low-income countries. Such Asylum Offsetting can be wrong in virtue of intentions, as when states send aid to refugees abroad to avoid accepting non-white refugees, and it can be wrong in virtue of its effects, as when states send aid less effective than offering asylum. I demonstrate that these wrongs can be avoided if states engage not in Asylum Offsetting, but in Moral Trades. Moral Trades arise when Y morally values φ-ing, X morally values ψ-ing, and X does φ in return for Y doing ψ (Ord 2015). In the context of refugee protection, a state X which values sending aid abroad might agree to grant asylum to many refugees, despite not valuing accepting these refugees, in return for another state which values asylum for refugees giving a large amount of aid abroad, despite this other state not valuing giving aid abroad. Moral trades avoid wrongs common in Asylum Offsetting, so long as no offsetting is involved. Offsetting can be involved in moral trades if one state X commits a wrong and offsets this with φ-ing, because Y values φ-ing, in return for Y offsetting its wrong with ψ-ing, because X values ψ-ing. For example, a state might wrongly use violence to deter refugees from arriving and offsets this by sending aid which Y values, but only if state Y which is wrongly refusing to send aid offsets this by accepting refugees which X values. I argue that policies should shift towards moral trades involving neither wrongs nor offsetting, but that moral trades with wrongs and offsetting are superior to moral trades alongside wrongs and no offsetting.


Past Events:

March 29, 2024, 10am ET (Zoom) Author Meets Critics: Jonathan Wolff (University of Oxford) and Avner De-Shalit (The Hebrew University of Jerusalem), City of Equals, Oxford University Press, 2024.

Access the book for free here!

Critics: Katarina Pitasse Fragoso (Goethe-Universität Frankfurt) and B.R. van Leeuwen (Radboud University)

Register

Abstract: When we think about equality in the city, we are very likely to think first of the wide and growing divide between rich and poor, in material terms. Yet when we think more about a ‘city of equals’ it becomes apparent that how people feel treated by the city and those around them, and whether they can live according to their values, are much more central. Accordingly, based on the authors’ reflections, a multi-disciplinary literature review, and, distinctively, more than 180 interviews in ten cities in six countries, the book offers an account of a city of equals based on the idea that it should give each of its city-zens a secure sense of place or belonging. Four underlying values structure this account. First, access to the goods and services of the city should not be based purely on the market. Second, each city-zen should be able to live a life they find meaningful. Third, there should be diversity and wide social mixing. Fourth, there should be ‘non-deferential inclusion’, that is, each person in the city should be able to get access to what they are entitled to without being treated as less worthy than others. They should be able to enjoy their rights without bowing and scraping, waiting longer than others, or going through special bureaucratic hurdles. In sum, in a city of equals each person is proud of their city and has the (justified) feeling that their city is proud of (people like) them.

April 13-16, 2022: American Philosophical Association 2022 Pacific Division Meeting

Session: Ethics of Public Policy: From AI to Freedom of Association

“Against Democratizing AI,” Johannes Himmelreich, Assistant Professor, Maxwell School of Citizenship and Public Affairs, Syracuse University

“Unbundling Freedom of Association,” Valerie Soon, Postdoctoral Fellow, McCoy Family Center for Ethics in Society, Stanford University

Moderator: Douglas MacKay, Associate Professor, Department of Public Policy, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

March 31, 2022, 10am EDT Author Meets Critics: Just Work for All: The American Dream in the 21st Century

Author: Joshua Preiss, Professor of Philosophy, Director of the Program in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, Minnesota State University, Mankato

Critics:

PPE Discount: To purchase book at 30% off, use promo code SS213 or JPS22 at checkout here.

Book Abstract: A book about the theory and practice of justice at a time of rising inequality and declining hope for a better future. As economic, technological, and political trends propel many countries further and further from a Smithian Well-Ordered Society (SWO) of rapid, broad-based gains from economic growth toward a Winner-Take-All Society (WTA) of slower growth, rising inequality, and declining absolute mobility, this book calls for renewed political and policy commitment to Just Work. Just work concerns the dignity of work and those who perform it, including the widely held conviction that individuals should be able to exchange hard work for at least a middle-class life for themselves and their families. By contrast with middle-income, middle-class is a context-relative normative standard that includes people’s status, power, and share of the benefits of economic growth.

Such a commitment is essential to combat the negative moral externalities of an economy where the fruits of growth are increasingly claimed by a relatively small portion of the population: slower growth, rising inequality, declining absolute mobility, dying communities, the erosion of social solidarity, lack of faith in political leaders and institutions, ethnic and nationalist backlash, the rise of authoritarian politics and parties, and the rapid rise in what economists Angus Deaton and Anne Case call deaths of despair. Covid-19 threatens to pour gasoline on these winner-take-all fires, further concentrating economic and political power in the hands of those best suited to withstand (and even profit from) the pandemic-driven economic crisis. In this book, I provide a model for understanding the American Dream and making it a reality in a post Covid-19 economy.